John Kilcullen
Copyright (c) 1996, R.J. Kilcullen.
Joseph Schumpeter (1883- 1950) was an Austrian economist who migrated to the United States in the 1930s. He made various contributions to economics, notably his History of Economic Analysis. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy was first published during World War II, in 1942. It applies his expertise as an economist to the great political issues of the day: after the depression of the 1930s the future of Capitalism was in question; the war was in defence of democracy; America's ally and rival, the Soviet Union, claimed to be a socialist state.
(The point made here - that the 'materialist theory of history' could be defended by introducing 'auxiliary hypotheses', but this is 'the beginning of the end' - was made more elaborately by Schumpeter's compatriot, Karl Popper, who suggests that what differentiates scientific from non-scientific thought is that science challenges falsification by experience and does not evade the test. See Popper, Conjectures and Refutations, pp. 34-37. Popper's views on this topic have led to much discussion among philosophers of science, the outcome of which seems to be that it is not possible to draw a line past which resort to auxiliary defensive hypotheses becomes demonstrably unreasonable, i.e. that there is no clear demarcation line between science and non-science; see Kilcullen, Sincerity and Truth: Essays on Arnauld, Bayle and Toleration, pp. 163-4. For criticism of Popper's philosophy of science see David Stove, Popper and After.)
In 'Marx the Economist' Schumpeter criticises the labour theory of value from the standpoint of modern economic theory (see my earlier lecture on the marginalist theory). The criticism boils down to this: the labour theory does not account for values in exchange except on special and unrealistic assumptions; if those assumptions are made, then the propositions of the labour theory follow from the modern theory, which can thus explain all the labour theory can explain; and the modern theory can explain things the labour theory cannot explain. See Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, pp. 24-9. Schumpeter also discusses various other aspects of Marx's theory and draws up a list of merits and defects. 'Adherence to an analytical apparatus that had always been inadequate and was in Marx's own day rapidly becoming obsolete, a long list of conclusions that do not follow or are downright wrong; mistakes which if corrected change essential inferences, sometimes into their opposites - all of this can be rightfully charged against Marx'. But 'Through all that is faulty or even unscientific in his analysis runs a fundamental idea that is neither - the idea of a theory... of the economic process... producing at every instant that state which will of itself determine the next one' (ibid, p. 43). (Schumpeter says that Marx was the first to try to do this. This is a surprising claim, that cannot be true except in some restricted sense. Comte and Mill wanted sociology to establish laws of the succession of states of society, and economists engaged in this project as early as Adam Smith.)
Schumpeter defends certain modern developments that have reduced the competitiveness of the capitalist economy. The neo-classical economists' analyses of the efficient allocation of resources in an equilibrium state are not of much practical interest, since conditions change so rapidly that the system never settles into equilibrium. The capitalist economy is swept by a 'perennial gale of creative destruction' (p. 84), a gale of innovation. 'A system - any system, economic or other - that at every given point of time fully utilizes its possibilities to the best advantage may yet in the long run be inferior to a system that does so at no given point of time, because the latter's failure to do so may be a condition for the level or speed of long-run performance' (ibid., p. 83). Monopolistic or oligopolistic practices or regulation may (may) contribute to long-run performance by encouraging innovation and other investment; unless the innovator believes that it will be possible to monopolize the advantage of innovation for a time, innovation will seem too risky. Compare patents, which encourage invention by promising inventors a temporary monopoly. 'Restrictions of this type are, in the conditions of the perennial gale, incidents, often unavoidable incidents, of a long-run process of expansion which they protect rather than impede' (p. 88). 'Largest-scale plans could in many cases not materialize at all if it were not known from the outset that competition will be discouraged' (p. 89). 'Perfectly free entry into a new field may make it impossible to enter it at all. The introduction of new methods of production and new commodities is hardly conceivable with perfect - and perfectly prompt - competition from the start' (p. 104-5). However, 'our argument does not cover all cases of restrictive or regulating strategy, many of which no doubt have that injurious effect on the long-run development of output which is uncritically attributed to all of them... Rational... regulation by public authority turns out to be an extremely delicate problem' (p. 91). Schumpeter has much else to say to those who believe that to deregulate and privatise, establish level playing fields etc., so as to foster maximum competition in the market place, is the way to achieve economic efficiency.
He begins (ch. 11, 'The civilization of capitalism') with a discussion strongly reminiscent of Weber of the connections between rationalism and capitalism: (1) Capitalism was produced by the urge to rationalize economic activity; (2) its success reinforces rationalism, and gives it a bent in certain directions - rationality comes to mean thinking for yourself, seeking individual self-interest, quantification, calculation, empirical science, positivism; (3) the spread of rationality in such a sense undermines traditional values and institutions, and eventually (4) undermines bourgeois values and institutions, i.e. undermines the legitimacy of capitalism itself.
As the development of capitalism proceeds the entrepreneur becomes obsolescent. (What Schumpeter says here is reminiscent of Weber on the 'routinisation of charisma'.) The modern giant corporation has corporate planning and research and development sections in which the firm's bureaucracy does what entrepreneurs did. 'Innovation itself is being reduced to routine' (p. 132). Schumpeter argues that 'this affects the position of the entire bourgeois stratum' (p. 134), even though the typical bourgeois is not an entrepreneur.
The development of capitalism eventually destroys the remnants of the feudal ruling class which it needs to carry on the functions of government, and especially to provide government functions with glamour and prestige. (Cf. Walter Bagehot, The English Constitution, ch. 2, 'The Monarchy'.) 'Without protection by some non-bourgeois group [in Weber's terms a status group], the bourgeoisie is politically helpless and unable not only to lead its nation but even to take care of its particular class interest' (p. 138). Destroying non-bourgeois strata was a matter 'of removing partners of the capitalist stratum, symbiosis with whom was an essential element of the capitalist schema... We might well wonder whether it is quite correct to look upon capitalism as a social form sui generis or, in fact, as anything else but the last stage of the decomposition of what we have called feudalism. On the whole, I am inclined to believe that its peculiarities suffice to make a type, and to accept that symbiosis of classes which owe their existence to different epochs and processes as the rule rather than as an exception... But there is no great objection that I can see to the opposite view' (p. 139).
Further, the progress of capitalism reduces the importance of the small producer and trader, and thereby erodes the meaning of 'property' and 'free contract', since property belonging to a giant corporation and contracts entered into with such a corporation do not have the same concreteness of meaning. 'This evaporation of what we may term the material substance of property - its visible and touchable reality - affects no only the attitude of holders but also that of the workmen and of the public in general. Dematerialized, defunctionalized and absentee ownership does not impress and call forth moral allegiance as the vital form of property did' (p. 142).
Intellectuals constitute a group 'whose interest it is to work up and organize resentment, to nurse it, to voice it and to lead it' (p. 145) against bourgeois institutions weakened by the developments just described. Intellectuals are 'people who wield the power of the spoken and the written word' in the 'absence of direct responsibility for practical affairs' (p. 147). The intellectual's 'main chance of asserting himself lies in his actual or potential nuisance value' (p. 147). Capitalism encouraged the growth and activity of the intellectual class by providing 'the support of the collective patron, the bourgeois public' (p. 149). The bourgeoisie may now wish to curb intellectual criticism of capitalism, but they cannot do so effectively. If a government tries to curb their criticism, 'the bourgeois stratum, however strongly disapproving some of their doings, will rally behind them because the freedom it disapproves cannot be crushed without also crushing the freedom it approves... In defending the intellectuals as a group - not of course every individual - the bourgeoisie defends itself and its scheme of life. Only a government of non-bourgeois nature and non-bourgeois creed - under modern circumstances only a socialist or fascist one - is strong enough to discipline them. In order to do that it would have to change typically bourgeois institutions and drastically reduce the individual freedom of all strata of the nation. And such a government is not likely - it would not even be able - to stop short of private enterprise' (p. 150). The expansion of higher education leads to the unemployment, under-employment or mis-employment of educated people; they become bitter critics of capitalist society.
'Labour never craved intellectual leadership but intellectuals invaded labour politics. They... supplied theories and slogans... radicalized it' (pp. 153-4). The worker distrust intellectuals: 'In order to get hold of him and to compete with non-intellectual leaders, the intellectual is driven to courses entirely unnecessary to the latter who can afford to frown. Having no genuine authority and feeling always in danger of being unceremoniously told to mind his own business, he must flatter, promise and incite, nurse left wings and scowling minorities, sponsor doubtful or submarginal cases, appeal to fringe ends, profess himself ready to obey - in short, behave toward the masses as his predecessors behaved first toward their ecclesiastical superiors, later toward princes and other individual patrons, still later toward the collective master of bourgeois complexion' (p. 154).
'The social atmosphere... explains why public policy grows more and more hostile to capitalist interests' (p. 154).
Bourgeois motivation also tends to die out from internal causes: One, mentioned above, is the evaporation of the substance of property. Another is the disintegration of the bourgeois family - unwillingness to sacrifice career and comfort to parenthood, consequent lack of interest in a home of the old type. 'The family and the family home used to be the mainspring of the typically bourgeois kind of profit motive'; without that motive the bourgeois 'loses the capitalist ethics that enjoins working for the future irrespective of whether or not one is going to harvest the crop oneself' (p. 160); 'The businessman's time-horizon shrinks, roughly, to his own life-expectation' (p. 161).
'The capitalist process not only destroys its own institutional framework but it also creates the conditions for another.... The outcome of the process is not simply a void that could be filled by whatever might happen to turn up; things and souls are transformed in such a way as to become increasingly amenable to the socialist form of life... In both of these respects Marx's vision was right' (p. 162).
Part 3 is entitled 'Can Socialism Work?'. The most important section is chapter 16, 'The socialist blueprint'. This answers the economists' objection that central planning cannot set rational priorities among the competing possible uses of the factors of production. Schumpeter shows that Socialism could adopt the market as the planning mechanism. Suppose the publicly-owned means of production are managed by managers who are instructed to aim at making a profit for their enterprise (the profit would of course belong not to them or to private owners or shareholders, but to the community); then the central board managing the allocation of productive factors will auction them off to factories etc. according to what they bid, factories etc. will produce what consumers will buy, consumer income will be wages from employment, employees will seek good wages, firms will offer wages according to prospective profitability, and so on as in the capitalist economy. What this argument shows is that from an economist's viewpoint there is nothing to choose between private enterprise and socialism: a market economy can exist whether the means of production are privately or socially owned. So socialism is as workable economically as capitalism.
'Market socialism' and democracy understood as competition between parties became popular demands in eastern Europe and the Soviet Union as the Communist regimes collapsed.
See Reading guide 10: Schumpeter
See The Philosophy of Free Entreprise: For and Against
Heilbroner, R, 'Was Schumpeter Right?', Social Research (H/1/.S53), 48 (1981), pp. 456-71
Return to Teaching
Materials on Political Thought
Return to Home Page