Copyright © 1996 R.J. Kilcullen
So in this lecture I want to make some comparisons between the writers we have been concerned with so far, and then say something about the history of ideas, and general history, of the period between these writers and the next one we will read, Augustine.
Thucydides gives a certain representation of what leading men among the ancient Greeks thought politics was about - competition, success and glory, in debate and in war. Like James Mill and Jeremy Bentham and many others, Thucydides assumes, or his characters do, that human beings are self-interested, that moral ideas have only a slight influence.
Plato provides a contrast with this view of Politics. Socrates is openly critical of Themistocles, Pericles, and Thucydides' other heroes. They did not make Athens powerful. Power is not ability to do whatever you fancy at the moment - the tyrant's power is useless because he does not know what to do with it. True power is the ability to achieve your most important goals. The goal is happiness, a worthwhile life; politics is cooperative action toward that goal. The statesman who really knows what politics is about does not seek his own fame and glory, but the true welfare of the citizens of the state. This requires knowledge of what a worthwhile life is like. Very few will achieve that knowledge, and only after long training and experience. The best state will be one ruled by a few genuine experts on the art of living well. Democratic politics is the struggle for glory and the useless power to tyrannize.
Aristotle's view of politics is like Plato's, only he does not seem so much concerned to change the world. The goal of all we do is happiness - a vague term, he says, and proceeds to give it content in a way which puts happiness out of the reach of large sections of the population. He does not actually say so, but it looks as if the aim of politics is the good life for a minority. His conception of happiness is a development of Plato's as seen in the Gorgias and Republic: its main element is intrinsically worthwhile activity, well done; so the virtues are needed to make it possible. The intrinsically worthwhile activities include those traditionally valued by the Greeks - courageous acts, generous acts, just acts, etc; also, and most important, intellectual activity -- science, philosophy, thinking, speaking. All this done with friends. This will be a pleasant life, but that is not what makes it valuable - these activities are valuable in themselves, and that is why those capable of them take pleasure in them. The aim of political activity is to establish and maintain cities in which that sort of life can be lived; and doing that is part of that sort of life - politics gives scope for the acts of courage, generosity, justice, etc., which are part of the good life.
As I mentioned, this good life is not attainable by more than a minority. It requires freedom and leisure for the political and intellectual activity in which happiness consists. Tradesmen, slaves, women and barbarians cannot live the good life. Aristotle takes a biological view of things. Nature is a principle of development toward a goal. What is natural is not what is widespread or original, but what you find in the fully-grown and well-developed specimen. If you want to know the goal for human nature, the good for man, look at the life of the upper stratum of Athens, at its best.
I remarked before that in comparison with Plato, Aristotle does not seem as much concerned to change the world. Plato's Academy was a revolutionary club, Aristotle's Lyceum was more like a university (as the Academy probably was by then). Perhaps Aristotle thought that nature could be left to take its course - perhaps it seemed to him that not much of importance could depend on an armed coup by a band of philosophers. Nature does nothing in vain. Aristotle studies nature - this is of course part of the intellectual life in which happiness partly consists. Among other aspects of nature he studies politics - how the different sorts of constitutions work, preserve themselves, undergo change. Aristotle's school produced monographs on 158 different constitutions. Only one survives, on the constitution of Athens; it is a combination of institutional analysis and history. So as well as being a political philosopher, he was a political analyst and historian. He also offers practical advice on how to preserve and stabilize whatever sort of constitution you have; e.g. he offers advice to tyrants. 'Avoid polarization' seems to be Aristotle's motto. Whatever the constitution, it will work better and last longer if it moves toward the middle, by incorporating elements of, or imitating, its opposite.
The Epicureans had reassuring words about the gods. They are not envious (cf. Herodotus, III.40, story of Polycrates). They do not maliciously and capriciously spoil the happiness of human beings. They get on with their own happy lives. Why should they trouble themselves about human beings? So there is no need to try to placate them, nothing to fear from them. In ancient times the Epicureans were generally described as atheists, but they did believe in the gods; but they held that we can live as if the gods do not exist (as the gods live as if we do not exist).
They also had a scientific theory, derived from an older philosophy (Democritus). Reality consists of a large numbers of atoms separated by void, full of nothing. These atoms move downwards, but from time to time they swerve (just by chance) and collide, and form complex things, which again dissolve as more movements and collisions take place. A human being is such a thing; death is dissolution, the soul is not (as Plato held) immortal, it is just a collection of atoms, there is nothing left to suffer, so there is no afterlife of which we need be terrified.
'These people want us to live like dogs'. Hence the name 'cynic', from the Greek word for dog.
Tyranny, slavery, freedom were important concepts in Stoic thought (see Epictetus). Freedom is not poverty, it is being able to give up external possessions and external freedom without distress. According to the Stoics the essential human freedom is inward: the ability to give or withhold assent to representations (thoughts) that come before my mind - to assent or not to the representation that something is so, or that the act it represents is to be done, or that the state of affairs represented is a good or an evil. I can always withhold my assent to such a representation - that is a power that cannot be taken away. I cannot prevent the removal of my property, the loss of a limb, the sensation of pain; but I can withhold by assent from the mental representation of these things as evils. Someone living perfectly in accordance with reason would feel the pain and perhaps some psychological disturbance, but would remain tranquil at the centre. Equanimity is the ideal. Emotion, or at least undue emotion, is to be repressed.
No one lives perfectly in accordance with reason: the 'wise man' is an ideal. The wise man is happy, i.e. is in possession of the good, no matter what happens to his possessions or body, because he would refuse to regard as really an evil anything but failure to act in accordance with reason. (The Stoic paradoxes - 'the wise man is happy on the rack', or in the bull of Phalaris: he feels the pain, and cries out, but knows all the time that this is not an evil.)
When Demetrius the city-sacker came upon the philosopher Stibo emerging from the flames of his city in which his wife and children had just died, he asked 'Did you lose anything?' Answer: 'No, all I possessed I have with me': 'meaning by this', Seneca says (Letter 9), 'the qualities of a just, a good and an enlightened character, and indeed the very fact of not regarding as valuable anything that is capable of being taken away.'
What does the wise man do when he is acting in accordance with reason? His actions aim at the same sorts of things as other people aim at, but he does ordinary things differently. According to the Stoics human beings all begin by seeking food, drink, and other things relating to self-preservation, but may come to make it a goal to seek these things 'in accordance with nature' or 'in accordance with reason'. This may become the over-riding goal (see Cicero, De Finibus, III.vi.21), so that we will endure the loss or frustration of the original self-preservation goals rather than do anything contrary to nature - i.e. would rather die than do anything contrary to nature. Seeking the original goals in accordance with nature or reason means seeking them in accordance with the individual's place as a part of the larger whole - of the human race, of the whole universe. Nature, for the Stoics, as for Aristotle, is a functional whole, with each part assigned its special role. Perhaps we can interpret the phrase 'act in accordance with nature, or reason' as 'act in accordance with the rules of morality', understanding that morality spells out the role human beings have to play in the system of nature. (The Stoics held a 'natural law' conception of morality.) So the Stoic seeks the same sorts of things as everyone seeks, but in accordance with the rules of morality; and his overriding goal is to act that way - if he does not attain the things he seeks, but has sought them properly, then he has all the same attained his goal.
According to the Stoics, actually to attain external things is not part of the good; the good is wholly to seek such things rationally. In Aristotle we can always substitute the term 'goal' for the term 'good' used as a noun - anything we aim at is a good, in Aristotle's terminology; but not in that of the Stoics. To express the point that the overriding goal is to act rightly even if we do not attain the things action aims at, the Stoics restricted the term 'good' to the goal of acting always in accordance with nature and would not apply the term to the things action aims at; they said that these things were 'to be preferred', but not that they were 'good'. Thus to stay alive is to be preferred, and the Stoic's actions will aim at keeping him alive, but not at any cost - only when that can be done in accordance with reason. Staying alive is not part of the good, though it is to be preferred. The good is something which cannot be taken away, as your life can be; the good is independent of outward circumstances; the things action aims at are not independent, but to act in accordance with reason is wholly within our power, and that is the good. The Stoics could perhaps have said that the ethical good is to act rightly, while success is good in some other sense; but to call both sorts of things good might suggest that they can be added together or subtracted - that right action with success is more good than unsuccessful right action. On the contrary, if a person always acts as he should as part of the larger whole - the human race, the universe - then his life is perfectly good, even if his outward circumstances are such that he does not achieve what is preferable. If his life is perfectly good, then he is happy - even if what he tries to do is not achieved.
The Stoics did not, like the Epicureans, seek security in the quiet, apolitical life. Stoic doctrine encourages political activity even in difficult circumstances. Even if success is improbable, the Stoic will engage in political action if that is the right thing to do. Of course reason may suggest that where there is little chance of doing any good in politics it would be better to turn to something else; but while political action seems for any reason to be his duty (e.g. to bear witness to principles or values), the Stoic will engage in it without being put off by lack of success. 'The wise man does not pity, but he helps' (i.e. he does not allow himself to become upset, since that would impede action, but helps in an unemotional way). Politics is one way of helping the human race (recall Plato's philosopher coming back down into the cave). Stoics sought political power, as other people did, but were resolved to use it rightly, in accordance with reason. Reason itself may dictate compromise, tact, avoidance of confrontation, etc.; but when it became clear that further compromise will do no good (rather, will not lead to anything 'preferable'), the Stoic will with equanimity lose his power and even his life.
According to the Stoics reason permits suicide, when there is no good to be achieved by living on. Socrates was one of the heroes of the Stoics: 'You are mistaken, my friend, if you think that a man who is worth anything ought to spend his time weighing up the prospects of life and death. He has only one thing to consider in performing any action - that is, whether he is acting rightly or wrongly, like a good man or a bad one' (Apology, 28b).
So Stoicism provided a doctrine of conscientious, principled, flexible, and resolute action in politics, in the face of danger.
In politics, as in ethics, freedom was a major value for the Stoics. They especially valued freedom in the sense of doing and saying what you think should be done and said (parrhesia, freedom of speech in the sense of outspokenness); under a tyranny, the only people free in this sense are those prepared to die - under any social arrangements, the free in this sense are those who are prepared to fail. But the Stoics also valued other sorts of political freedom; they supported monarchy, but not tyranny. Outward freedom is 'to be preferred', but is not essential to the good life. External enslavement cannot destroy the freedom everyone has to give or withhold assent and to live in accordance with reason. Whereas the good life as Aristotle conceived of it could be lived only by someone with freedom and leisure, not by slaves, artisans, women, barbarians, the Stoics taught that anyone can live the good life now, wherever he or she may be, and can continue living it no matter where - on the rack, in the bull of Phalaris.
For more on the Stoics see A.A. Long, Hellenistic Philosophy [B/525/.L66], and A.A. Long and D.N. Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers, vol. 1 [B/505/.L66/1987]; E.V. Arnold, Roman Stoicism (B/528/.A7); R. MacMullen, Enemies of the Roman Order, chs. 1 and 2 (Harvard, 1966) [DG/78/.M33]; M.T. Griffin, Seneca, a Philosopher in Politics (Oxford, 1976) [PA/6675/.G75]
So the practice of the sceptics ('seekers') is to suspend judgment. If (as the Stoics say) the wise man affirms nothing but what is certain and cannot be wrong, then he can make no affirmations and must suspend judgment: or, some of them said, he may affirm what seems to him, but only as what seems to him, not as something certain. This is enough for practical purposes. The sceptic acts on what seems to him to be the case, without affirming that it really is so - whether it is he can never know. The Greek word for a doctrine or teaching is dogma; the Stoics were a dogmatic school - not meaning pig-headed, but simply philosophers who make affirmations. Were the sceptics also, despite themselves, dogmatic, in affirming that nothing should be affirmed, in claiming to be certain that nothing is certain? No, they replied, we merely say that it seems to us that nothing is certain, and that nothing should be affirmed as certain, though some things are good enough to act on.
On the sceptics see Long, and Long and Sedley, cited above; also M. Schofield, M. Burnyeat and J. Barnes (eds.), Doubt and Dogmatism (B/525/.O68); M. Burnyeat (ed.) The Skeptical Tradition (B/837/.S56). On scepticism see Kilcullen, Sincerity and Truth: Essays on Arnauld, Bayle and Toleration [B/1824/.A864/.K57], essay IV, 'The ethics of belief and inquiry'.
Augustine recognises the (neo-)Platonists as closest to the beliefs of Christians, especially because they were not materialists (as Epicureans and Stoics were), but held that there are immaterial or spiritual realities (recall Plato's Theory of Forms); see City of God, VIII.5-.
Return to Teaching
Materials on Political Thought
Return to Home Page