INTRODUCTION
Copyright © 1996 R.J. Kilcullen
"The Middle Ages" refers to the period of European history from
the end of the Roman Empire in Italy until the Renaissance, i.e.
from the 5th century A.D. until the 15th. Philosophers during this
time included Boethius, Anselm, Peter Abelard, Thomas Aquinas,
Duns Scotus, William of Ockham and many others. During the 12th
and 13th centuries European philosophy was much influenced by the
writings of Muslim philosophers including Avicenna (ibn Sina) and
Averroes (ibn Rushd). Philosophy in the medieval style continued
into the late seventeenth century; Descartes and Leibniz cannot be
well understood without some knowledge of medieval thought.
PHIL252 is concerned with medieval thought from Boethius to Thomas
Aquinas, PHIL360 Later Medieval Philosophy with the period from
Duns Scotus, including the medieval elements in 17th century
philosophy.
I SOME HISTORICAL BACKGROUND
The Hellenistic Period
Between Aristotle (who died in 322 B.C.) and the earliest medieval
philosopher, Boethius (A.D.480-524), a good deal happened of which
it will be useful to have some idea. Greek armies led by Alexander
"the Great" (died 323 B.C.) overturned the Persian Empire and
established a number of Greek Kingdoms in its territories, which
included Egypt, Palestine, Syria and Asia Minor. The culture of this
period is called "Hellenistic"; the Greeks called themselves
"Hellenes"; the "ist" suggests that Hellenistic culture was close to
but not identical with Classical Greek culture. In the Hellenistic
world Greek was for many people a second language, Greek culture was
something learnt in school. There was plenty of work for
professional teachers of Greek language, literature, history,
philosophy, mathematics, medicine, astronomy and other branches of
science. Many of the teachers had themselves learnt Greek as a
second language. Their writings included aids for the newcomer to
Greek culture: dictionaries, digests, handbooks, encyclopedias,
explanatory commentaries of various sorts. The city Alexander had
founded in Egypt, Alexandria, became an important centre of Greek
culture, with schools and a famous library, the Museum. Alexandria
was especially important as a centre of study in mathematics,
science, medicine and philosophy. Athens continued to be a centre of
philosophy, but not of the sciences.
From Plato's time there had been opposition between philosophy
and rhetoric - between philosophy, mathematics, science, medicine
on the one hand, and rhetoric and literary studies (poetry, drama,
history) on the other. Except in Alexandria, Hellenistic culture
was in the rhetorical tradition: as was that of ancient Rome, of
Byzantium of Europe until the 12th century, and of the European
Renaissance of the fifteenth century. Greek philosophy and science
was taken up in Islamic countries, and in Europe between the
twelfth and fifteenth centuries.
The Romans
The last Greek ruler of Egypt, Cleopatra, died in 30 B.C. By then
the Romans controlled the eastern Mediterranean region, including
Greece, Palestine and Egypt. But Latin did not displace Greek in
those regions. In fact, the Romans themselves had been Hellenized.
Educated Romans learnt Greek and went to Athens and other Greek
centres to complete their education. Latin literature was an
imitation of Greek literature: Latin poetry, drama, history and
oratory followed Greek models. However, there was no Latin
counterpart of Greek mathematics, science and medicine, and not much
philosophy. The orator and politician Cicero wrote a number of
interesting and valuable works of philosophy in Latin which are
believed to be based on Greek originals since lost. In these works
Cicero sometimes remarks on the difficulty of finding Latin
equivalents for Greek philosophical terms. Other writers of
philosophical works in Latin were Lucretius and Seneca. Apart from
these three there was little or nothing. During the Roman period a
good deal of philosophy was still written in Greek, some of it in
Rome - by Epictetus, by Plutarch, by the Roman emperor Marcus
Aurelius, and by Plotinus.
Christianity
In the Greek-speaking eastern Mediterranean a major event was the
spread of Christianity. Palestine had been included in one of the
Greek Kingdoms established after Alexander's conquests; on the
conflicts between Greek and Jewish culture see the books of the
Maccabees (in R.S.V. Common Bible, (Collins, 1973),
Apocrypha/Deuterocanonical Books, p. 122 ff). The Jewish scriptures
were translated into Greek by Jews living in Alexandria. The
Christian New Testament was written in Greek. Paul, himself a Jew,
travelled throughout the eastern Mediterranean preaching the
Christian gospel in Greek to Greek-speakers, many of them Jews.
Christianity spread rapidly in the Greek-speaking east, and also in
Rome, at first among Greek-speaking residents, later among speakers
of Latin.
Christianity produced a large literature of its own, some of
which is significant for the history of philosophy in the middle
ages, either because it conveyed Greek philosophical ideas to
later Christian readers, or because its religious content
suggested new philosophical questions or theories. The basic
Christian book was the Bible, which consisted of the Jewish
scriptures (called by Christians the "Old Testament") together
with new Christian books (the "New Testament" - the four Gospels,
the Acts of the Apostles, Letters, and the Book of Revelation).
The rest of the Christian literature of the early centuries (first
to sixth) is called "Patristic", i.e. "of the Fathers" (patres)
of the Church ("Fathers" in the sense of early leaders). The most
influential patristic authors included Athanasius, Chrysostom,
Gregory Nazianzen, Gregory of Nyssa and Origen, who wrote in
Greek, and Ambrose, Augustine, Jerome and Gregory "the Great", who
wrote in Latin. (A reference book: Johannes Quasten, Patrology
(Utrecht, 1966 ff), Ref/BR67.Q3.)
Among Christians "Trinitarian" and "Christological"
controversies arose involving Greek philosophical concepts.
Concerning Jesus Christ it was debated whether he was both God and
man, whether he had two natures, how these two natures were
related, whether he had a human soul; and concerning God, how the
Christian belief in the divinity of Christ and the Holy Spirit can
be reconciled with the doctrine that God is one ("one substance").
These questions were discussed at several "General" or
"ecumenical" ("world-wide") Councils of Christian bishops, held at
Nicaea, Constantinople, Ephesus and Chalcedon. Those who accepted
the decision of these councils regarded themselves as "orthodox"
("right-teaching") or "Catholic" ("found everywhere") and the
others as heretics (under various descriptions - Arians,
Nestorians, etc.). [Note 1]
The Byzantine Empire
In 324A.D. Constantine became emperor, the first emperor to become a
Christian. He moved the capital of the Roman Empire to the Greek
town of Byzantium, renamed New Rome or Constantinople (now
Istanbul). It is customary to call the medieval empire of the Greeks
"Byzantine" from the original name of their capital; they called
themselves Romaioi, Romans. The old Rome, and its Senate,
Consuls and other magistrates, kept great prestige, but it was no
longer the seat of government. In fact the Empire had been for a
long time too large to be controlled and protected from one capital;
it extended from Britain to Syria, from the Danube to North Africa.
The common language of the eastern half was Greek, of the western
half Latin. Emperors had sometimes taken colleagues and assigned
parts of the Empire to them. In some places peoples from outside the
Empire ("barbarians") - Goths, Vandals, Huns, Franks etc. - forced
their way in or infiltrated. Sometimes they were employed as
mercenaries or auxiliaries, who were sometimes only nominally
subordinate to the Roman Emperor in Constantinople. thus in Italy in
the fifth century there were western emperors subordinate to the
emperor in Constantinople, but Italy was in fact controlled by the
Goths (who were Arians, heretical Christians). In A.D. 476 the Goths
deposed the last western Roman emperor (this date is sometimes given
as the end of the Roman Empire and the beginning of the Middle
Ages), but continued to profess allegiance to the Emperor in
Constantinople. [Note 2] The
emperor Justinian (A.D.527-565) tried, with some temporary success,
to re-establish control over the west; the "Gothic Wars" fought by
his generals Belasarius and Narses in Italy devastated the country
and are sometimes said to mark the real beginning of the "dark ages"
in Italy. Justinian (one of the few eastern emperors to speak Latin)
also attempted to re-establish Roman law; his legal experts prepared
a Latin Code of Roman Law, a Digest of the
teachings of the Roman legal writers, and Novels of new
legislation, and Justinian himself wrote (or gave his name to) the Institutes
or introductory textbook.
Islam
From the seventh century the Roman Empire came under attack from the
followers of the prophet Mohammed (died 632A.D.). Islam became the
religion of the middle east, north Africa and part of Spain. Jews,
dissident Christians (heretics) and a few orthodox Christians
continued to live in these countries; knowledge of Greek medicine
gave some of them access to Muslim rulers. The language mainly used
for literary purposes by Muslims was Arabic. Greek medical,
scientific and philosophical writings, including the works of
Aristotle, were translated into Arabic, sometimes by way of Syriac -
some of the translators were Syrian Christians. In 9th century
Baghdad scholars in the "House of Wisdom", under the Caliph's
patronage, made or corrected translations of Greek, Persian and
Indian writings. In 12th century Spain many of these writings,
together with original works in Arabic, were translated into Latin,
sometimes with the help of Jews who knew Arabic.
See The Dictionary of the Middle Ages (Ref/D114.D5)
articles "Translation and Translators"; also F.E. Peters Aristotle
and the Arabs (B744.3.P43), pp. 35 ff. and 58 ff.
The Holy Roman Empire
Meanwhile in the West, in A.D. 800, the pope had proclaimed Charles
"the Great" (Charlemagne), King of the Franks, "Roman Emperor",
since Charles, and not the emperor in Constantinople, was the
effective military protector of Rome. This Roman empire came
eventually (in the 10th century) into the possession of the princes
of Germany: when an incumbent died the princes elected a successor,
who went to Rome to be crowned by the pope and then returned to
Germany. In practice the emperor in the west had little authority
even in Germany, and the Kings of France, England and Spain, and
many cities in Italy, denied his claims; in the thirteenth century
the popes claimed jurisdiction over the emperors. Throughout the
middle ages there were, then, two "Roman Empires", one in
Constantinople and the other in Germany. The "Holy Roman Empire of
the German People" lasted until it was abolished by Napoleon; the
Roman Empire in the east lasted until the capture of Constantinople
by the Muslim Turks in 1453. The political and linguistic division
between the two empires was a religious division also; in 1054 the
Latin Catholic and Greek Orthodox churches excommunicated one
another.
The Carolingian Renaissance
Charlemagne presided over a literary revival that modern scholars
call the Carolingian renaissance. See E.S. Duckett, Carolingian
Portraits (Ann Arbor, 1962), DD131.D8, and Alcuin,
Friend of Charlemagne (New York, 1951). The language of
culture, of the church, and of bureaucracy was Latin, but for most
people in Europe after the "barbarian invasions" Latin was a foreign
language. Charlemagne encouraged literacy in Latin, his own clergy
being helped in this work by Anglo-Saxon and Irish monks, who had
already had to develop methods of teaching Latin as a second
language. [Note 3] Carolingian
scholars made the copies of the Latin classics which the humanists
later discovered. They used an elegant script they had developed,
which the humanists thought was the script used by the ancient
Romans (our lower-case print, still called "Roman") - the humanists
thought they were discovering texts written by the ancient Romans
themselves and not read during the middle ages, whereas in fact they
were finding texts copied and studied by medieval scholars. During
the 9th-11th centuries pirates from the north (Danes, Vikings,
Norsemen) did considerable damage, but the spread of Latin learning
then resumed. As a result of the Carolingian renaissance, schools
multiplied; at first they were often established in monasteries and
cathedrals, later in many towns. By the twelfth century schools
existed in most of the towns of Italy, France and England. Many
schools were businesses, from which the master made his living out
of students' fees.
The renaissance of the twelfth century
Another movement that historians call a renaissance took place in
the twelfth century. See C.H. Haskins, The Renaissance of the
Twelfth Century (Cambridge, Mass., 1955), PA8035.H3. The
"Renaissance of the Twelfth century" was in part a revival of Greek
philosophy. Two things seem to have produced this movement. The
first was an increasing sophistication in studies of law in Italy,
due perhaps to the growth of commerce. Teachers of law sought out
the few extant copies of the Corpus iuris civilis, the
compilation of Roman law made at the direction of Justinian. More
copies were made, and glosses and increasingly elaborate
commentaries were written to help students through the obscurities
of Justinian's corpus. [Note 4] A
law-education industry grew up centred on Bologna. Scholarly and
teaching techniques already worked out in ancient times in the study
of law and other subjects were revived or reinvented in the law
schools and were taken over (or independently developed) in other
schools. These included the gloss (explanations
between the lines of obscure words or phrases, or more elaborate
comments in the margin), the commentary with
division of the text ("In the first part he does so-and-so, in the
second part, beginning at "..." he does such-and-such"), and the question
(authorities and arguments on one side, authorities and arguments on
the other side, and solution).
The second possible cause of the Renaissance of the Twelfth
Century was contact between Latin Christians and Muslims (also
with Jews and Greek-Orthodox Christians). The contact was of
course to a large extent violent, but incidentally Christians
formed a favourable impression of the medicine and material
culture of the Muslims and became curious about their medical and
other science. They soon discovered that the Arabic literature and
these fields was based on translations of Greek writings. In the
twelfth century there was a flood of translations into Latin,
first from Arabic and then from Greek, first of works of medicine,
science and astrology, and later of philosophy. The philosophy did
not include Plato, but it included the treatises of Aristotle, a
few of which had long before been translated by Boethius.
Universities
In some of the larger towns where there were many schools
"universities" were formed. A university was not itself a teaching
institution. It was an association of masters each of whom ran his
own school as a business, getting his income from the fees of
students enrolled in his school. The university approved new masters
and set the curriculum to ensure the reputation of the schools of
the town so as to attract students; it tried to set rents and other
prices, using the bargaining power with the townspeople that masters
had because of the business the schools brought to the town. By the
13th century universities existed in Bologna, Paris, Oxford, and
elsewhere. These urban schools were the public for the new
translations of Greek and Arab philosophy and science, and in turn
the influx of translations attracted more students to the schools.
The Church at first opposed the teaching of Aristotle, but student
demand prevailed and soon the universities made Aristotle's works
the set texts in the Arts curriculum. Although the Church supervised
the universities and the masters and students were all clerics (in a
minimal sense), the teaching was not mainly religious. The most
flourishing schools were in law and medicine ("the lucrative
faculties"); at a time when Paris had over one hundred Arts schools
it had only eight in theology. The study of the law flourished
especially in Italy. It was encouraged by the "Roman Emperors", i.e.
the German princes who claimed that title, because of the support
Roman law in Justinian's version gave to the Emperor. The law of the
Catholic Church, "Canon law", was also a flourishing study in the
Italian law schools, encouraged by the pope, whose authority it
reinforced. Philosophy was studied especially in the Arts schools of
Paris and Oxford.
II EVALUATIONS OF MEDIEVAL CULTURE
The Renaissance View of the Middle Ages
"Medieval" conveys contempt; to say that some arrangement is
"medieval" is to express emphatic disapproval. "Medieval" was a term
of disparagement from the beginning. It was invented in the 15th
century by the Italian humanists, who believed they were bringing
about a rebirth (renascentia) of the ancient and better
culture of the Greeks and Romans after a "middle" or intervening
period of barbarism, the dark age. According to the humanists the
ancient Roman Empire had been destroyed by barbarian invaders such
as the Goths and Vandals. The humanists called the culture of the
middle ages "Gothic" to suggest its barbarian origin. As indicated
above, more recent historians have found two earlier "renaissances",
the Carolingian renaissance and the renaissance of the twelfth
century; the "dark age" has now shrunk to the period between the
"barbarian invasions" and the ninth century.
The "humanists" were so called because of their study of literae
humaniores, "more humane literature", the studia
humanitatis ("of humanity"). Humanitas was an
ancient Roman term with various meanings, including "mental
cultivation befitting a man, liberal education, good breeding,
elegance of manners or language, refinement" (Lewis and Short, Latin
Dictionary). "Befitting a man", suggests a human
being fully developed as a human being should be. The other terms
the dictionary uses - "liberal" (i.e. appropriate to liber,
a free man, as distinct from a slave), "good breeding",
"elegance", "refinement" - suggest that the ideal human being is
an upper-class gentleman, witty, urbane, at ease, self-confident,
a good conversationalist. Nothing laboured, pedantic, technical,
incompatible with leisure, fitted this ideal. The literae
humaniores therefore did not include the technical
treatises of Aristotle, mathematics, astronomy, law or
architecture, but only genres that a gentleman might practice:
speeches, dialogues, letters, essays, histories, poetry, drama. In
recommending the literae humaniores the humanists means
to contrast their own gentlemanly studies with the laborious and
technical studies of "the schools" (i.e. the universities) fit
only for pedants and plebeians - law, medicine, theology and
especially Aristotelian philosophy and science. Philosophy was of
course a study for gentlemen, but the humanists thought it should
be carried on in relaxed style in dialogues, essays or letters,
not in laborious "scholastic" genres such as the
treatise, disputed question or commentary on a text. The
humanists' philosophers were Plato, Cicero and Seneca, not
Aristotle.
It is easy to sympathise with some of the points the humanists
were making: that education should develop the "humanity" of
students, that it should not be excessively specialised or
vocational, that educated people should be able to discuss in a
relaxed and interesting way a wide range of subjects. On the other
hand there are some subjects that cannot be pursued properly
except in a technical way. The success of the humanist movement
was a set-back to philosophy, mathematics and science (which had
begun to develop in the late medieval schools of philosophy).
In fact, the humanists themselves had a vocational interest.
They or their pupils sought employment with the Italian cities,
and later with other governments, as secretaries and ambassadors;
they could write letters, write speeches, converse and were better
trained for such things than the graduates of the universities. On
one view their campaign against the education of the schools was
an attempt to make obsolete and unfashionable the "product" sold
in this labour market by the established "firms".
In another view the contest between humanists and scholastics
was another phase of the battle that had been going on since
Plato's time between philosophy and rhetoric. In his dialogues Gorgias
and Phaedrus Plato had criticised the rhetoricians as
being concerned not with truth but with persuasion. His
contemporary, Isocrates, had in opposition maintained that the
study of the art of making speeches should be at the centre of
education. Plato himself, and later Aristotle and Cicero, had
suggested that the true rhetorician will try to persuade hearers
to the truth and must therefore be a student of the truth. But
still there remains a contrast between seeking truth for the sake
of knowledge and understanding and seeking truth so as to be more
persuasive: for that purpose verisimilitude is better than truth.
In the ancient world the rhetorical education prevailed. In
Plato's Academy and in Aristotle's school, the Lyceum, philosophy,
mathematics and science were cultivated together. But during the
Hellenistic period most of the schools taught mainly rhetoric and
other subjects useful to a speechmaker (including some parts of
philosophy). The exception was Alexandria, where all branches of
philosophy, mathematics and science were still cultivated. In
Hellenistic Rome education was rhetorical, and Latin literature
did not include any counterparts of the difficult treatises
studied in Alexandria. At the beginning of the medieval period
Boethius first translated into Latin some of the treatises of the
Alexandrian schools, thereby providing medieval Latins with a
basis from which they could appropriate the rest of the
philosophical and scientific heritage of the Greeks in the twelfth
century when it became available to them from Muslim sources.
The renaissance humanists, then, were reviving the rhetorical
culture of ancient Rome, studying Latin works written then and the
Greek writings that Cicero and his contemporaries would have read,
in opposition to the more technical Greek writings, oriented to
understanding rather than to persuasion, which had meanwhile
become in translation the basis of education in the medieval
universities.
Against some prejudices remaining from the humanist campaign:
- The Renaissance of the 15th century did not for the first time
revive the whole of Greek and Latin culture. Rather, it
transferred interest from the philosophical-scientific culture
that had been revived three hundred years earlier to the
literary and rhetorical culture which had been revived earlier
still in the "Carolingian renaissance" and then displaced during
the renaissance of the twelfth century.
- For most branches of technical philosophy the 15th century
Renaissance was a set-back. The gentlemanly genres -
dialogue, letter, essay - imposed by the humanists were less
suited to rigorous thinking than were the scholastic genres
of question, treatise and commentary.
- The Renaissance did not stimulate the development of science;
rather it transferred attention from science to literature and
may even have been a setback for science. [Note 5]
- Medieval Europe was not closed against influence from
non-Christian authors. Muslim and ancient Greek philosophy and
science were taken up with enthusiasm.
- Medieval culture was not entirely religious and otherworldly.
The universities were business enterprises responding mainly to
secular interest in philosophy, medicine and law with theology a
comparatively minor subject.
- The influence of Aristotle's authority over the Scholastics
was greatly exaggerated by their humanist critics. Aristotle's
books were at first opposed by the Church but became university
set books because of student demand. It was always understood
that much of Aristotle's philosophy was at odds with
Christianity. And as we will see, medieval philosophy was much
influenced by neo-Platonism.
The Enlightenment
The Renaissance humanists spoke of their age of light succeeding a
dark age. The metaphor was taken up again, especially in France,
from the late 17th through the 18th century, the Age of
Enlightenment. The "enlightenment" movement was directed especially
against the Catholic Church and was concerned especially with
religious tolerance and other aspects of what is now called
liberalism. (Key events in the late 17th century were the revocation
of the Edict of Nantes and the repression of Huguenot (Calvinist)
churches in France, and the victorious war fought by the Protestant
powers of northern Europe led by William of Orange against France -
a conflict still remembered in northern Ireland.) The philosophes
denounced the religious intolerance of the Catholic Church as
medieval and Gothic, reminiscent of the medieval Inquisition.
Did freedom of thought exist in the middle ages? Unless it did,
at least in some measure, genuine philosophy can hardly have
existed. The answer seems to be that although in the middle ages
freedom of thought was not acknowledged as a right, it did exist
in some measure, at least in the universities, even in the faculty
of theology. To elaborate: (1) Theologians and canon lawyers held
that Christian belief was for every human being a duty, though
failure to believe (like failure in other duties) might be excused
by invincible ignorance. However, the excuse of ignorance could
not be available to anyone who had once believed: to abandon the
Christian faith after believing it was held to be always wrong
and, if persisted in, deserving of punishment. On the other hand,
(2) it was held that no one who was not a Christian could rightly
be coerced into belief. But (3) non-Christians could not be
allowed to try to convert Christians, and (4) could not be allowed
to practice their religion in public. On these points see Thomas
Aquinas, Summa Theologiae 2-2, q. 10 and q. 11.
Point (1) implies that heretics - that is, persons who had once
been Catholics but have abandoned part or all of the Christian
faith - should be punished. But it was held that to be a heretic
it was not enough to believe a heresy (i.e. a doctrine
inconsistent with Catholic faith); it was necessary also to be
"pertinacious", i.e. not willing to be corrected. A Catholic who
adopted an heretical opinion but would abandon it if he or she
realised it was heretical was not a heretic. This made freedom of
thought possible within limits: although no Catholic could examine
Catholic belief to decide whether it was true, it was
permissible to think about and discuss questions to which some
answers might be heretical without fear of becoming a heretic: it
was enough to be ready to be corrected. It became customary for
authors to make "protestations" of readiness to be corrected. [Note 6]
Although it was not permissible for
Christians to examine the Christian faith and decide that it was
not true, it was permissible to construct arguments addressed to
non-believers to show that Christian belief, or some part of it,
was true, and it was also permissible to criticise and
refute such arguments. The obligation was to believe,
not to have arguments. Christianity (like Judaism and Islam)
claimed to be based on revelations from God: that is, adherents
believed that God sent messengers (e.g. the prophets, Jesus) to
tell mankind things they could not have discovered by unaided
natural reasoning - the "gospel" (good news). Many theologians
held that there were good reasons for believing these messengers,
and that it was possible, once the message was believed, to
achieve by reflection some understanding of its content - perfect
understanding only in the next life, but some understanding even
in this life. But no one was obliged to have good reasons for
believing or to attain any particular level of understanding. The
obligation was to believe the message. A Christian could therefore
say, without falling into heresy or unbelief, that some argument
offered to support or explain Christian belief was unsound. [Note 7] Thus there was freedom
to criticise such arguments as long as it was not inferred from
the failure of some argument that the Christian faith was not
true.
Freedom of thought was also helped by the fact that philosophy
was recognised as a distinct discipline. The Arts schools taught
philosophy and not religion. The text books were written by
philosophers who had not been Christians. Theologians were Arts
graduates and their writings in theology were full of philosophy
(in fact much of the most interesting philosophy in the middle
ages is to be found in theological works, such as Thomas Aquinas's
Summa theologiae), but they knew which arguments were
based on Christian revelation and which were based on "natural
reason". Christian writers sometimes wrote books in which the
arguments were deliberately restricted to those that natural
reason could supply: for instance, Boethius's Consolation of
Philosophy, Saint Anselm's Monologion, [Note 8] Proslogion and
Cur deus homo, [Note 9] and
the first three books of Thomas Aquinas's Summa contra
gentiles. [Note 10] The
distinctness of philosophy as a discipline did not mean that there
were two truths; the conclusions of philosophy were expected to be
consistent with the truths of religion. But there was no objection
to saying: "This is what philosophical reason seems to establish,
though it can't be true since it contradicts the faith"; Ockham
and other 14th century writers sometimes write like this.
Finally, the teaching methods in the schools and some of the
content of the textbooks encouraged the practice of looking for
and trying to answer objections, including objections to things
held by faith. In the schools one of the main exercises was
disputation, the "question"; some of the students would be given
the task of defending some proposition, others the task of
objecting to it; after some debate the master would give his
answer and reply to the objections that had been brought against
it. In preparation for the role of "opponent" senior students
would gather a repertory of objections, the stronger the better.
Aristotle's works suggest by example and precept [Note 11] that opposing views
should be carefully examined.
In the arguments for and against in the first part of a
"question" there are many quotations from "authorities", that is
writers who were well regarded in the schools; often the
authorities are put in opposition to one another. However the
decision of the question was not by authority, except on points of
faith where the bible and Church councils were decisive
authorities (but not Church fathers or other theologians - see
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, part 1, q. 1, art. 8,
ad 2). Thomas Aquinas says that authority does not prove
demonstratively but forms an opinion through belief (Quodlibet
3, art. 31, ad 1). He says that in disputations in the schools, of
which the purpose is to achieve understanding, arguments must be
used that get at the root of the truth and show how it is true; if
the master "determines" the question merely by authorities the
hearer can be certain that the conclusion is correct, but gains no
knowledge or understanding and goes empty away (Quodlibet
4, art. 18). Thomas Aquinas's teacher, Albert, in reference to a
text from Hilary (one of the Church fathers), wrote: "Some say
that Hilary retracted these words . . . But since we have not seen
his book of Retractations, it is therefore necessary to
bring force to bear (vim facere) on his words in three
places . . ." (In 3 Sent., d. 15, a. 10). It was usually
possible to adapt an authority to what the writer regarded as the
truth. (The texts above are quoted, and the whole issue discussed,
in M.D. Chenu, Toward Understanding St. Thomas (Chicago,
1964), chapter 4.)
The nineteenth century
Until the late 17th century higher education in Europe included
study of philosophical writings in the medieval tradition, but
during the 18th century knowledge of medieval thought became
uncommon because medieval culture was regarded with so much
contempt. [Note 12] In the 19th
century, however, a revival of interest took place. This is
explained partly by the revival at that time of the Christian
churches, including the Catholic Church; Catholics began to take
pride in their medieval heritage, including scholasticism. In the
late 19th and early 20th centuries, during what was called the
"modernist" crisis, Church authorities made the doctrine of Thomas
Aquinas the basis of instruction in seminaries to prevent too much
compromise with modern philosophical thought. This Catholic revival
of interest led to great advances in knowledge of medieval thought,
though there was some distortion due to modern religious
preoccupations.
A second cause of renewed historical interest in medieval
thought was the change of attitudes to history associated with the
Saint-Simonian movement in France and Hegelianism in Germany.
Under the influence of these movements, historians no longer
measured earlier cultures against their own and pronounced them
defective where they were different; instead, they tried to see
each "period" as an organic whole and as a necessary stage in the
development of human history. They therefore tried to understand
medieval thought "from within", so to speak, and without being in
too much hurry to pass judgment on detached bits of it.
The twentieth century
During this century the revival of interest has continued. Religious
reasons for interest in medieval thought have perhaps become less
influential. A lot is now known about a large number of medieval
writers and about the currents of opinion and controversies of those
times. It now seems that there is as much value in the study of
medieval philosophy as there is in the study of Greek philosophy.
And my approach in this course will be the same as it would be in a
course on Greek philosophy: we will read and analyse a selection of
texts with the purpose of understanding and evaluating the
arguments, without being in any hurry to draw general conclusions,
either about the spirit of medieval philosophy or about the
philosophical issues with which the texts are concerned.
Reference conventions
- References to Plato - e.g. Republic 595a -
are by title of dialogue and "Stephanus number" (corresponding
to the pages and subdivisions of pages ("a", "b" etc.) of the
sixteenth century edition of Plato by Etienne (Stephanus)) - in
the example to the text corresponding to Etienne's page 595,
subdivision a. Stephanus numbers will be found down the side (or
across the top) of modern translations.
- References to Aristotle - e.g. Physics
VIII.6, 259 a4 - are by title, "book" and chapter, and the
"Bekker number" found in the margin of modern translations - in
the example to the text corresponding to page 259, left hand
column, line 4, in book VIII chapter 6 of Aristotle's Physics
in the edition of Immanuel Bekker (Berlin, 1831).
- The Bible is referred to by "book", chapter and verse
(usually separated by a colon, sometimes by a full stop;
sometimes the chapter is in small Roman numerals). Thus 1 Cor.
13:4 (or 1 Cor. xiii.4) is the fourth verse of chapter 13 of the
first book called Corinthians. It reads: "Love is
patient and kind; love is not jealous or boastful". A list of
the books of the bible is usually found in the front of the
volume.
- Other ancient authors are usually referred to by
title, "book" (a subdivision of what we would call a
book, i.e. the work) and chapter. Often there are two
overlapping chapter divisions, long and short: the long chapter
is referred to by small Roman numeral and the short by Arabic
numeral. Thus Augustine, Confessions VII.xii.18 refers
to book VII chapter xii or (in the other chapter division)
chapter 18. Note also: "ff" means "following"; "cf." means
"compare"; "viz." means "namely".
Return to Teaching
Materials on Medieval Philosophy
Return to home
page